What Is Socialism? Socialism and Philosophy

March 3, 2019
This is the first in a series of four presentations on “What is Socialism?” Shorter versions will be published in News & Letters. The essay below in our series is “Socialism and Philosophy.” The second essay is “Socialism, labor and the Black dimension”; the third is “Socialism and ecology”; and the last is “Socialism and Women’s Liberation.”
♦♦♦
 by Gerry Emmett
The world economic crisis that began in 2008 and continues today, Trumpism, Brexit, the European Far Right coming to power or contending seriously forstate power in so many countries, the election of Bolsonaro in Brazil, who identifies with this reactionary movement, the genocidal attacks on the Syrian Revolution by Putin and Iran: all this is inspiring young people, especially, to reach out for an oppositional concept to this horrific reality.
 
Thus we see the growth of Democratic Socialists of America with multiple tendencies within it. We also see their internal debates over how to respond to what’s happening in Syria, which I consider to be the test of world politics, including especially “socialist” politics. Other historic trends are also returning to the scene: Maoism, for example, which I would not consider as being a good thing.
 
It raises a question, obviously: what is socialism? This talk tonight raises another question, too: what is philosophy? This is where I wish to begin, with the young Karl Marx.
 
First, he is a Hegelian—he is building on Hegel’s dialectic of Second Negativity, the negation of the negation, as self-determination.
 
Freedom. All of world history, for Hegel, was a history of the progress and consciousness of freedom. This is how Marx understands philosophy. And he sees philosophy in terms of something new that has come into the world, the struggle of the working class—as representative of humanity—to become free.
 
What Hegel had seen as the epochal change brought about by the French Revolution, Marx saw as being deepened by the struggle of the workers. This meant a new role for philosophy as well.
 
Previously, the “new” that had entered the world was revealed religion. Thus, philosophy had been considered the “handmaiden” of theology for centuries (theology being the handmaid’s tale of philosophy). Modern times, the Enlightenment, brought science to the fore, and for many thinkers, both before and after Marx, philosophy became subordinated to science. This remained true of many Marxists, for example, Louis Althusser and his school.
 
Hegel himself had a critique of the Enlightenment opposition between faith and science. What is significant here is that Hegel placed philosophy above revealed religion—that is, in an Absolute that embodied the social individual, the human being experiencing history as humanity’s own self-development. With this insight the young Karl Marx begins to grapple with the working class movement for freedom, socialism.
 
This was the foundational question in Marxism. For Marx, socialism, or communism, or humanism (words he used fairly interchangeably) was a matter of philosophic mediation. When Marx singles out the proletariat as the revolutionary subject, in 1843, it is as “a sphere which has a universal character by its universal suffering and claims no particular right because no particular wrong but wrong generally is perpetrated against it…which…is the complete loss of [humanity] and hence can win itself only through the complete rewinning of [humanity].” This includes new relations between people as well as between humanity and nature.
 
This is in his critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right. Marx soon spells this out, in his 1844 Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts, as humanism, as the social individual that is the new subject of an appropriated dialectic of freedom. Note that it isn’t only the proletariat singled out as the subject of “wrong generally” but also woman—“the infinite degradation in which [humanity] exists for [itself]… has its unambiguous, decisive, plain and undisguised expression in the relation of man to woman.” In singling out these new subjectivities we see Marx going beyond Hegel, concretely, while building on his revolution in philosophy.
 
The impact of the American Civil War will inspire Marx’s re-organization of volume 1 of Capital. Hegel had already written in his Philosophy of Right that “a slave has an absolute right to free himself…I am entitled to the union of my potential and my actual being.” Despite real contradiction in Hegel, and his acceptance of certain racist ideas of the “science” of his time time, the principle of self-determination penetrated far beyond his empirical ignorance.
 
Anti-slavery, thus anti-racism, is fundamental to the very concept of both the “proletariat” and Marx’s humanism. These relations of philosophy, subjectivity, and objective realty become central to Marx’s lifetime of theory and practice, right up to his late writings on non-industrial societies and the role of women in history. His own critique of socialism is spelled out in the 1875 Critique of the Gotha Program of German socialism: it demands the end of the division between mental and manual labor, and anything less than this will fall short of real self-determination. It stamps Marx’s entire life’s work as a form of philosophic intervention in history.
 
Capital itself is structured very carefully. The “freely-associated labor” that strips away the commodity form is inextricable from the Absolute General Law of accumulation of capital, as well as from the “so-called ‘primitive accumulation’” of slavery and genocide. This structure is a concrete development of that “wrong generally,” that “infinite degradation” of humanity, and its transcendence. That inextricability is a philosophic projection of humanism. It is the absolute embodied in the social being.
 
This is socialism for Marx.
 ****
 The question arises again, very concretely, in the early 20th century debates over the nature of imperialism, the collapse of the Socialist International in World War I, and the dialectics of the Russian Revolution. The dialogue included names as prominent as Vladimir Lenin, Rosa Luxemburg, Leon Trotsky, Bukharin, Kautsky, and Hilferding and their varieties of socialism.
 
In the face of these issues, as well as anti-colonial revolts in Ireland, China, India, the Middle East and Central Asia, Lenin felt compelled to return to Hegel’s dialectic to work out practical positions on imperialism and national liberation. He realized that “none of the Marxists have understood Marx.” Of course, these questions of imperialism and national liberation became central to the anti-colonial freedom movements in Africa, Asia, and Latin America. They reach for philosophic expression in the work, for example, of Frantz Fanon in the 1950s and ‘60s.
 
To be brief: in the absence of a serious re-organization of thought, and with Lenin’s own philosophic ambivalence leading him to keep his Philosophic Notebooks to himself, the Bolsheviks in power failed to negotiate the 1920s and the development of state-capitalism. Some even created a non-Marxist economic category of “primitive socialist accumulation of capital,” which would have appalled Marx with both its incoherence and its anti-humanism.
 
The door was opened for the world historic disaster of Stalinism with its millions of victims.
 
****
 
What is socialism? was raised again in Eastern Europe in the post-World War II era. Then Marxist humanists like Leszek Kolakowski, Karel Kosik, and Egon Bondy made an explicit return to Marx’s philosophic writings as opposed to the alienation they experienced living under Russian Communist rule and state-capitalism. It was an attempt to reform Communism from within, which came to be called “socialism with a human face” in Czechoslovakia.
 
In Hungary it saw the participation of the Petofi Circle and Georg Lukacs in the Hungarian Revolution.
 
Polish thinker Kolakowski pointed out that this version of Marxist humanism was also in conflict with narrow nationalism (of the sort that holds power in Poland today and erects statues of Kolakowski). This Marxist humanism did represent the search for new human relations among the masses of people. However, in the 1980s, the significant Marxist humanist Mihailo Markovic in Yugoslavia fell into this narrow nationalism, in Serbia, a huge retrogression that laid a groundwork for the Bosnian genocide of the 1990s.
 
This retrogression arguably became the basis around which world reaction reorganized itself. We hear its echoes everywhere today.
 
In general, “socialism” that only amounts to state ownership and planning will be disastrous—it is change that remains within alienation. Venezuela today would be another example of this. The “Bolivarian Revolution” began with promise as the entire population voted in a new Constitution that had many good aspects, but reliance on the world market for oil (in contradiction to the Constitution’s focus on environmentalism) and a cult of “the Leader” created disaster.
 
The founder of Marxist-Humanism in the U.S., Raya Dunayevskaya, wrote a 1987 essay on “A Post-World War II View of Marx’s Humanism…” for a YugoslavEncyclopedia of Contemporary Socialism. She recognized the growth of reaction and counseled: “The self-development of ideas cannot take second place to the self-bringing forth of liberty, because both the movement from practice that is itself a form of theory, and the development of theory as philosophy, are more than just saying philosophy is action. There is surely one thing on which we should not try to improve on Marxand that is trying to have a blueprint for the future.”
 
One reason I find Raya Dunayevskaya’s Marxist-Humanism so compelling is because it represents the point of connection between these two historic moments, and these two philosophic interventions—the Russian Revolution and the struggle over its meaning and direction, and the critique of state-capitalism calling itself “socialism” from within.
 
In confronting the role a form of Eastern European Marxist humanism played in instigating the Bosnian genocide, we have learned much, I would argue, about both philosophic responsibility and the necessity for philosophic intervention in history.
 
Marxist-Humanists didn’t create the idea of defending a multi-ethnic Bosnia of Muslims, Serbs, Croats, Jews and Roma coexisting. What we did was make a philosophic category of that defense that still resonates—that is necessary for understanding the world. We heard that category come to life again in the revolutionary chant of “The Syrian people are one!” that opposed the fascist dictator Assad’s efforts to divide the people along sectarian and ethnic lines, efforts that depended on the bourgeois world’s racist past and present. 
**** 
I would argue that the Arab Spring revolts were in fact the most powerful challenge to the current stage of world reaction. How much bigotry was erased when workers in Madison, Wisconsin, in 2011 sought to walk like the Egyptians in Tahrir Square? It was a great moment, for those of us who were part of this movement, and it was something picked up by the people of Kafranbel, Syria, for example, who made a point of continuing the dialogue with humanity through their weekly sign and slogan demonstrations just as Marx had recognized that all revolutions reach out to “the true community, the human community.”
 
The Occupy movements that followed in its wake were a new expression of internationalism that, unfortunately, lacked the theoretical dimension which could have built solid relations between the working classes of the U.S., Europe, the Middle East and beyond.
 
When the human connection was made, it was, as one Chicago socialist activist described in connection with the 2011 May Day immigrants’ rights demonstration inspired by Tahrir Square, “electrifying.” It truly was.
 
But too many Leftists went into Occupy with the attitude that they had to begin from square one to “educate” people in socialist ideas. They missed the point that the masses were actually inventing something new and world-historic that was in fact nothing less than a “dress rehearsal” for the world revolution.
 
The Syrian Revolution was the turning point, and it occasioned another failure to successfully define what is socialism. Very few Leftists of any stripe supported that revolutioneven when it was exemplary on any terms, non-violent and explicitly non-sectarian. Many Leftists in Occupy Chicago and elsewhere argued against that internationalism which was inherent in the movement.
 
As I said, it was a failure to theorize what was arising from the mass movement. Syrians have called consistently for solidarity from “the true community, thehuman community.” They have called in the name of freedom, of Enlightenment, of religion, of anarchism, and of socialism. It is what Frantz Fanon termed the untidy affirmation of an absolute—how sad for the “socialist intellectual” who is cheated of his familiar language, and receives only the thing in itself. Only the millions of people willing to risk all for their freedom.
 
Without this humanist philosophic mediation, we see that socialism is fated to remain one more form of human self-alienation.
 
As before, the failure to answer this question, what is socialism?, has horrific consequences. Those who suffer these consequences can never be allowed to become an historic elision, any more than the victims of slavery and genocide who are so poignantly remembered and recognized as absolute in Marx’s Capital.
 
This seems to me to be the debate over what socialism can mean today.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *